Julian Sanchez header image 2

photos by Lara Shipley

A Postscript on Nozick

June 22nd, 2011 · 15 Comments

Responding to yesteday’s post, Matt Yglesias argues that Stephen Metcalf is still kinda on point because, even if Nozick remained a libertarian on some grounds—maybe pragmatic or consequentialist ones—he nevertheless abandoned the deeper philosophical opposition to redistributive taxation that characterizes Anarchy, State, and Utopia. Matt does, however, back off when I point him to pages 281-282 of Nozick’s final (2001) book Invariances, where Nozick writes:

The different levels of ethics have a different status. The ethics of respect, largely specified by what I have called the core principle, is the part, the one part (I think), that is (that should be) mandatory across all societies. In saying this, I am putting forward a particular normative position: that the further ethical levels are matters of personal choice or personal ideal. Even if these further levels are not mandatory for all societies, some particular society may attempt to make one or another of these further levels [requiring affirmative assistance to others, caring and love, and embodiment of various spiritual ideas] mandatory within it, punishing those members of the society who deviate or fall short. I also believe—this is an additional component of my own position, presented in Anarchy, State, and Utopia—that no society should take this further step. All that any society should (coercively) demand is adherence ot the ethics of respect. The further levels should be matters for a person’s own individual choice and development.


Yglesias actually thinks this view is arguably more extreme than the original A,S,&U position, though since Nozick’s primary concerns in that chapter are metaethical, I’d be chary of inferring too much from his passing remarks here. Still, it’s clear enough that he regards this aspect of the position laid out in A,S,&U as “his position.” In what sense, then, do we think he became “less hardcore,” and in what sense did he regard his earlier views as “seriously inadequate”? While it’s probably a mistake to try to shoehorn too much of what a thinker as notoriously mercurial as Nozick wrote into a single coherent view, given the span of time involved, I think it’s useful to consider the position laid out in Invariances in light of what Nozick says in “The Zig-Zag of Politics,” which is the essay that gave rise to the popular impression that Nozick had wholly shed his libertarian ideas. I’ll return to that momentarily.

First, an observation about Invariances. Here, Nozick spells out a view of morality as an evolved adaptation with a specific function: Enabling ever broader mutual social cooperation. He divides this cleanly into “levels,” but it’s not obvious that the boundaries are so sharp and clean as all that. On his “core principle of ethics,” for instance, Nozick writes:

It is desirable to extend the realm of people who benefit from coordination and cooperation. A group G1 should extend social cooperation to G2, if this can be done in some way that benefits those in G2 and improves (or does not worsen) the situation of the poeple in G1. [….] However, a group is not required to extend cooperative relations to another group with whom it has no interactions, at the cost of lessening the benefits to itself.

Now, pace Nozick, it seems at least possible to me that this principle is compatible with some forms of affirmative assistance. It might, for instance, be the case that the (or a) Pareto optimal scenario for interaction between a Better Off and Worse Off group, on the whole and over the long term involves some level of subsidy from Better Off to Worse Off, in the form of provision for education or insurance against extreme hardship, because the social surplus from the productive cooperation thereby enabled—and in particular the share of the surplus accruing to Better Off—is greater than the amount of the subsidy. (It may also be less expensive than enforcing libertarian rights against members of Badly Off who may feel compelled to turn to crime in the absence of viable opportunities for productive cooperation.) Where this is the case, that sort of limited aid might fall within Nozick’s “core principle” even when it is not motivated by an independent principle requiring aid to others for its own sake, at least if that principle is interpreted broadly. If familiar collective action problems make it difficult to supply an adequate subsidy without compulsory transfer, the initial interaction will not be to the “mutual benefit” of those compelled to provide it, but the system of interactions it enables may be. I don’t say this is the case with respect to any particular system of transfers—that’s an empirical question—but insofar as this scenario is not wildly implausible, it is at any rate subject to reasonable disagreement. What falls within the “level” specified by the “core principle” of interaction to mutual benefit is, in other words, not quite so sharply defined as the system of side-constraint rights spelled out in A,S,&U—and my loose interpretation of it may well be in direct conflict with what he says in response to Rawls in Chapter 7 of that book—even though there are enough obvious affinities between these ideas that Nozick himself is prepared to link his “core principle” with the position of the earlier book.

Turning back to “The Zig-Zag of Politics,” I note that one of its primary concerns has to do with the attitude one ought to have in the context of a liberal democratic society in which many different moral views coexist. Where A,S,&U is concerned with ideal theory and the sort of government that could justly arise from a state of nature, “Zig-Zag” is more concerned with how to deal with the range of divergent positions members of a pluralistic society holds. Here, he effectively takes a fallibilist stance that leads him to embrace the titular Zig-Zag of democratic politics over intransigent insistence on one’s own view as uniquely avoiding injustice, at least within a certain range. In some ways, it prefigures the Rawls of Political Liberalism, who focuses on how to deal with the conflict of diverse reasonable moral conceptions.

We hear echoes of this in Nozick’s language in Invariances. In contrast with the stark boundaries of rights-respecting and rights-violating states found in A,S,&U, we find a discussion of multiple levels of ethics, all of which are equally part of morality, even as Nozick argues that only one level is legitimately enforceable. There is, in other words, a stronger sense of tension between competing values: A state which coercively transfers resources to the poor may be enforcing a real ethical obligation even if that enforcement violates the claim to non-interference embedded in the “ethics of respect,” and even if we think those claims should take priority. That seems to mark an important distinction from simple theft, even if we think the transfer is on net morally bad.

Note also the (perhaps canny) ambiguity in the claim that “some particular society may attempt to make one or another of these further levels mandatory,” though he believes no society “should” do so. Does that “may” express a mere possibility, or a permission, as in “it is not the morally optimal policy, but it is in the set of morally permissible options”? (Would that make libertarianism supererogatory?) One way to construe this, again borrowing Rawlsian jargon, is as suggesting that (some modified version of) the view from A,S,&U is one among many “reasonable conceptions of justice” that might order a liberal society, and in Nozick’s view the most defensible one of that set. This is something analogous to the way Rawls recasts the theory of Justice as Fairness articulated in A Theory of Justice as one of several possible “modules” that may be plugged into the superstructure of Political Liberalism.

Since something close to this is roughly my own view, I’m wary of too-confidently projecting it on a thinker who is, sadly, no longer around to correct the liberties I take with his ideas. Still, it is one (I think appealing) way to square Nozick’s claim that he had become “less hardcore” with the textual evidence that his substantive commitments to a moral (and not merely pragmatic) claim against coercive state redistribution remained intact. (There are also, as David Boaz notes, reports that Nozick had modified his views on the inalienability of certain rights.) On this interpretation, Nozick’s substantive view of libertarian rights remained largely the same, but less “hardcore” insofar as that view is situated within a family of reasonable views that give different weights to competing ethical values, rather than simply in contrast to varying degrees of theft, slavery, and predation.

Tags: General Philosophy · Libertarian Theory


       

 

15 responses so far ↓

  • 1 Jason Kuznicki // Jun 22, 2011 at 3:10 pm

    I’d always thought Nozick’s rather extreme stance on the alienability of rights in AS&U sat badly with libertarianism. In particular it sat badly with the idea of rights as side constraints.

    In a society with meaningful side constraints, certain rights just wouldn’t be alienable, and contracts far along on the slavery-to-demoktesis spectrum would revolt the conscience of most individuals. They accordingly wouldn’t be enforced.

    This is also what we see the practice of actual liberal democracies.

  • 2 One link on Metcalf-Nozick | Bleeding Heart Libertarians // Jun 22, 2011 at 3:18 pm

    […] Nozick, while vaguely planning out how to write about it on the blog. While I still plan that, here’s a link to a fantastic Julian Sanchez post that’s of direct BHL […]

  • 3 .@mattyglesias & @normative (& infinitesimal me) on the metcalf/nozick hubbub « eyes open // Jun 22, 2011 at 5:13 pm

    […] like the idea of a Nozick that recognizes ethical obligations to a community, CATO research fellow Julian Sanchez takes pains to point out that no matter who Nozick had Matt reading in class, in his last writing on the ethical […]

  • 4 .@mattyglesias & @normative (& infinitesimal me) on the metcalf/nozick hubbub « eyes open // Jun 22, 2011 at 5:13 pm

    […] like the idea of a Nozick that recognizes ethical obligations to a community, CATO research fellow Julian Sanchez takes pains to point out that no matter who Nozick had Matt reading in class, in his last writing on the ethical […]

  • 5 Tim W. // Jun 23, 2011 at 5:37 am

    Rather than relying on an “ethics of respect,” Kant himself claimed that coercion was justified if it is met the conditions necessary to secure a system of right (recht) (including securing the universal right of freedom, which is freedom compatible with everyone else’s freedom). While the state cannot aim directly at redistribution, contemporary kantians who are inspired by the Doctrine of Right (and Rawls and Nozick and many famous 1980s philosopher are inspired by the Groundwork, so do not count) can indirectly support redistribution as a means to secure the conditions of right. Briefly, the conditions of right are the conditions of legitimacy of the state, and Kant using the idea of the original contract to say these are things I must be able to possibly agree to. As moral person, I am only subject to the laws I will or at least those laws I will along withothers. I can only be subject to legislation that stems from my will along with others if these wills (including my own) are independent wills. They are not wills dependent on others. So the conditions of legitimacy (that I am not subject to anything other than independent willing) require all citizens to be independent. To secure these conditions, the state (in Rousseau like fashion) might have to make sure inequalities are not too great (though no homogeniety is needed in Kant). Under some contemporary Kantian interpretations of the Doctrine of Right (again not Rawls), this supports using means of redistribution to achieve the conditions of legitimacy. So, patterned principles are not allowed. But something like either Lomasky or perhaps even Anderson’s democratic equality (reducing inequality to make it possible for people to be citizens) could be supported under Kantian principles (again, not ethical principles per se. The ethics of respect could probably support this whole line of argument itself, though, as the “Right” is heavily allied with respect).

    I’m just roughly sketching this out, so I might have made some mistakes. On Kant, I highly recommend ch. 11 on social justice in Allen Wood’s book Kantian Ethics

    http://www.scribd.com/doc/47866169/Kantian-Ethics-CUP-2008-Allen-W-Wood

  • 6 Pithlord // Jun 23, 2011 at 1:17 pm

    Once you abandon the alienability principle, how does the Chamberlin argument still work? I could agree that he has the right to his talents and labour, but not that he has the right to sell them on any terms. Maybe he only has the right to sell them on the condition he pays a progressive income tax on what he makes.

  • 7 Julian Sanchez // Jun 23, 2011 at 1:57 pm

    Nozick came to think that SOME rights are inalienable, presumably under narrow sets of circumstances, not that they generally are.

  • 8 Pithlord // Jun 23, 2011 at 5:56 pm

    I get that, and indeed Nozick is in agreement with pretty much everybody on that point. Presumably, Karl Marx thought it was OK to sell his copyright in journalistic pieces to left-wing newspapers.

    But if having a right *entails* having a right to alienate that right, then I can see how self-ownership implies no coercive redistribution. But if no such entailment exists, then Wilt can 100% own his basketball ability without necessarily 100% owning what he can get for his basketball ability.

  • 9 What’s Really Wrong with the Wilt Chamberlain Argument? // Jun 28, 2011 at 4:16 pm

    […] RSS photos by Lara Shipley ← A Postscript on Nozick […]

  • 10 sac à main // Aug 26, 2011 at 3:12 am

    Welcome to http://www.replicabagsell.com .Our company was founded in 2004 and was committed to internet marketing businesses in 2006.

  • 11 Constance // Feb 23, 2012 at 12:24 pm

    Late to this reading/discussion, but I can’t think of any better way to summarize my thoughts about Nozick’s writing–which I thoroughly enjoy–than Montaigne’s “All I say is by way of discourse, and nothing by way of advice. I should not speak so boldly if it were my due to be believed.”

  • 12 Julian Sanchez // Feb 24, 2012 at 1:40 pm

    I think that was very much Nozick’s own attitude to his own writing: That it was more interesting and fruitful to explore what might be the case, and what would follow from it, than to insist on having rigorously solved, once and for all, some central philosophical problem

  • 13 More on Lomasky, Taxation, and Reasonable Disagreement | Bleeding Heart Libertarians // Jun 26, 2014 at 9:01 pm

    […] UPDATE: Julian Sanchez reminds me that Robert Nozick’s essay, “The Zig-Zag of Politics,” makes many points quite similar to Lomasky’s. See Julian’s thoughtful discussion here. […]

  • 14 Melissa // Dec 16, 2016 at 2:13 pm

    Parabens Google, você é um adoslecente,. e ainda vai ajudar a muita gente de alguma forma. Agradeço muito por você existir, você faz parte da minha vida . Meu adolescente querido .BeijoUsando Internet Explorer 9.0 em Windows 7

  • 15 Alex // May 9, 2017 at 5:46 pm

    „Turning back to “The Zig-Zag of Politics,” I note that one of its primary concerns has to do with the attitude one ought to have in the context of a liberal democratic society in which many different moral views coexist. Where A,S,&U is concerned with ideal theory and the sort of government that could justly arise from a state of nature, “Zig-Zag” is more concerned with how to deal with the range of divergent positions members of a pluralistic society holds.”

    After reading “The Zig-Zag of Politics” this interpretation also cross to my mind, but then I realized what he has said in the footnote on the page 287. There he directly confronts the theory elaborated in A,S & U claiming that there is a “major area – there may be others – where that theory went wrong”. Here he refers to the collective action through government, that is the importance and in a way (moral) inevitability of it.

    So it is obviously not just the matter of attitudes or levels of investigation but comparison of different theories and their evaluation of the phenomenon he labels “acting through government”. Now he thinks that something is wrong with the older theory and not that the theory is related to the different level of investigation.